On April 11,
I’ll be giving the Princeton Anscombe
Society 10th Anniversary Lecture, on the subject “Natural Law and the Foundations of Sexual Ethics.” Prof. Robert George will be the
moderator. Details
here.
Thursday, March 12, 2015
Saturday, March 7, 2015
Capital punishment should not end (UPDATED)
Four
prominent Catholic publications from across the theological spectrum -- America
magazine, the National Catholic Register, the National Catholic
Reporter and Our Sunday Visitor -- this week issued a joint
statement declaring that “capital punishment must end.” One might suppose from the statement that all
faithful Catholics agree. But that is
not the case. As then-Cardinal Ratzinger
famously affirmed
in 2004, a Catholic may be “at odds with the Holy Father” on the
subject of capital punishment and “there may be a legitimate diversity of
opinion even among Catholics about… applying the death penalty.” Catholic
theologian Steven A. Long has issued a
vigorous response to the joint statement at the blog Thomistica.net. (See also Steve’s
recent response to an essay by “new natural law” theorist and capital
punishment opponent Christopher Tollefsen on whether God ever intends a human
being’s death.)
Apart from
registering my own profound disagreement with the joint statement, I will for
the moment refrain from commenting on the issue, because I will before long be
commenting on it at length. My friend Joseph
Bessette is a professor of government at Claremont McKenna College. Joe and I have for some time been working together
on a book on Catholicism and capital punishment, and we will complete it
soon. It will be, to our knowledge, the
most detailed and systematic philosophical, theological, and social scientific
defense of capital punishment yet written from a Catholic perspective, and it will
provide a thorough critique of the standard Catholic arguments against capital
punishment.
William Wallace, OP (1918-2015)
Fr. William
A. Wallace has
died. Wallace was a major figure in
Aristotelian-Thomistic philosophy of nature and philosophy of science, and the
author of many important books and academic articles. Still in print are his books The
Modeling of Nature: Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Nature in Synthesis
(a review of which can be found here), and The
Elements of Philosophy: A Compendium for Philosophers and Theologians.
Among his many other works are his two-volume historical study Causality and Scientific Explanation, the
classic paper “Newtonian Antinomies Against the Prima Via” which appeared in The
Thomist in 1956 (and is, unfortunately, difficult to get hold of if you
don’t have access to a good academic library), and a collection of some of his
essays titled From a Realist Point of
View. An interview with Wallace can be found
here, and curriculum
vitae here. Here is the text of a
series of lectures by Wallace on philosophy of nature, and here is a YouTube
lecture. Some of Wallace’s articles are
among those linked to here. RIP.
Thursday, March 5, 2015
Nyāya arguments for a First Cause
As I noted
in an
earlier post, arguments for a divine First Cause can be found in Indian
philosophy, particularly within the Nyāya-Vaiśeșika tradition. They are defended by such thinkers as Jayanta
Bhatta (9th century A.D.), Udayana (11th century A.D.), Gangesa
(13th century A.D.), and Annambhatta (17th century A.D.). Translations of the key original texts and
some of the most important studies in English are not easy to find, but useful
discussions are readily available in books like Kisor Kumar Chakrabarti’s Classical
Indian Philosophy of Mind: The Nyāya Dualist Tradition, Ben-Ami
Scharfstein, A
Comparative History of World Philosophy, and Parimal G. Patil’s Against
a Hindu God: Buddhist Philosophy of Religion in India.
Friday, February 27, 2015
Descartes’ “indivisibility” argument
In the sixth
of his Meditations
on First Philosophy, Descartes writes:
[T]here is a vast difference between
mind and body, in respect that body, from its nature, is always divisible, and
that mind is entirely indivisible. For
in truth, when I consider the mind, that is, when I consider myself in so far
only as I am a thinking thing, I can distinguish in myself no parts, but I very
clearly discern that I am somewhat absolutely one and entire; and although the
whole mind seems to be united to the whole body, yet, when a foot, an arm, or
any other part is cut off, I am conscious that nothing has been taken from my
mind; nor can the faculties of willing, perceiving, conceiving, etc., properly
be called its parts, for it is the same mind that is exercised [all entire] in
willing, in perceiving, and in conceiving, etc. But quite the opposite holds in corporeal or
extended things; for I cannot imagine any one of them [how small soever it may
be], which I cannot easily sunder in thought, and which, therefore, I do not
know to be divisible. This would be
sufficient to teach me that the mind or soul of man is entirely different from
the body, if I had not already been apprised of it on other grounds.
Monday, February 23, 2015
Braving the web
The 10th
Annual Thomistic Seminar for graduate students in philosophy and related
disciplines, sponsored by The Witherspoon Institute, will be held from August 2
- 8, 2015 in Princeton, NJ. The theme is “Aquinas and Contemporary Ethics,” and faculty include John Haldane, Sarah
Broadie, and Candace Vogler. Applications
are due
March 16. More details here.
Does academic
freedom still exist at Marquette University?
The case of political science professor John McAdams, as reported by The
Atlantic, Crisis magazine, and Slate.
The late Fr.
Richard John Neuhaus is the subject of a
new biography by Randy Boyagoda. Review
at National
Review, and podcast of an interview with Boyagoda at
Ricochet.
Thursday, February 19, 2015
Augustine and Heraclitus on the present moment
On the
subject of time and our awareness of it, Augustine says the following in The Confessions:
But how
does this future, which does not yet exist, diminish or become
consumed? Or how does the past, which
now has no being, grow, unless there are three processes in the mind which in
this is the active agent? For the mind
expects and attends and remembers, so that what it expects passes through what
has its attention to what it remembers…
Suppose I
am about to recite a psalm which I know. Before I begin, my expectation is directed
towards the whole. But when I have
begun, the verses from it which I take into the past become the object of my
memory. The life of this act of mine is
stretched two ways, into my memory because of the words I have already said and
into my expectation because of those which I am about to say. But my attention is on what is present: by
that the future is transferred to become the past. (Confessions
11.28.37-38, Chadwick
translation; an older translation is available online here)
Friday, February 13, 2015
Accept no imitations
Given that
he’s just become a
movie star, Alan Turing’s classic paper “Computing Machinery
and Intelligence” seems an apt topic for a blog post. It is in this paper that Turing sets out his
famous “Imitation Game,” which has since come to be known as the Turing
Test. The basic idea is as follows:
Suppose a human interrogator converses via a keyboard and monitor with two
participants, one a human being and one a machine, each of whom is in a
different room. The interrogator’s job
is to figure out which is which. Could
the machine be programmed in such a way that the interrogator could not determine
from the conversation which is the human being and which the machine? Turing proposed this as a useful stand-in for
the question “Can machines think?” And in
his view, a “Yes” answer to the former question is as good as a “Yes” answer to
the latter.
Friday, February 6, 2015
What’s the deal with sex? Part II
In a
previous post I identified three aspects of sex which manifestly give it a
special moral significance: It is the means by which new human beings are made;
it is the means by which we are physiologically and psychologically completed
qua men and women; and it is that area
of human life in which the animal side of our nature most relentlessly fights
against the rational side of our nature.
When natural law theorists and moral theologians talk about the procreative and unitive functions of sex, what they have in mind are the first two
of these aspects. The basic idea of
traditional natural law theory where sex is concerned is that since the good
for us is determined by the natural ends of our faculties, it cannot be good
for us to use our sexual faculties in a way that positively frustrates its procreative and unitive
ends. The third morally significant
aspect of sex, which is that the unique intensity of sexual pleasure can lead
us to act irrationally, is perhaps less often discussed these days. So let’s talk about that.
Tuesday, January 27, 2015
What’s the deal with sex? Part I
In the
second edition of his book Practical
Ethics, Peter Singer writes:
[T]he first thing to say about ethics
is that it is not a set of prohibitions particularly concerned with sex. Even in the era of AIDS, sex raises no unique moral issues at
all.
Decisions about sex may involve considerations of honesty, concern for
others, prudence, and so on, but there is nothing special about sex in this
respect, for the same could be said of
decisions about driving a car. (p. 2, emphasis added)
Thursday, January 22, 2015
Links of interest
Has
mathematics misled modern science? Bryan
Appleyard, channeling physicist Lee Smolin and philosopher Roberto Mangabeira
Unger, makes
the case.
But maybe
mathematical elegance should trump empirical evidence? Some physicists seem to think so. In Nature,
physicists George Ellis and Joe Silk will
have none of it. Further commentary,
and a roundup of other responses, from physicist
Peter Woit.
At the OUP
Blog, John Searle on
the intentionality of perceptual experience. At the same blog: Federica Russo and Phyllis
Illari on causation in
science and Tad Schmaltz on
causation in Aristotle and Hume.
Philosopher
John Lamont on Thomism, “manualism,” and the nouvelle théologie, at
Rorate Caeli.
Monday, January 19, 2015
Schall on Scholastic Metaphysics
At Crisis magazine, Fr. James V. Schall very
kindly reviews my book Scholastic
Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction. From the review:
Feser has done his homework. He is quite familiar with modern analytic
philosophy along with other modern systems. He came to Aristotle and Aquinas, whom he
knows well, from his realization of problems in the modern systems. Likewise, Feser is acquainted more than most
with the various texts that were once profitably used in Catholic university
and seminary philosophy departments but later abandoned during the last half
century. Feser recognizes that these
writers, who were perhaps not perfect, were often very good thinkers in their
own right as well as familiar with the intellectual tradition of the West…
Saturday, January 17, 2015
Feynman’s painter and eliminative materialism
In case you haven’t
been following it, my
recent critique of novelist Scott Bakker’s Scientia
Salon essay on eliminative materialism
has generated quite a lot of discussion, including a series of vigorous and
good-natured responses from Bakker himself both in my combox and at his own
blog. Despite the points made in my
previous post, Bakker still maintains -- utterly implausibly, in my view --
that the incoherence objection begs the question against the eliminativist. To see the problem with this response,
consider a further analogy.
Friday, January 16, 2015
2015 Aquinas Workshop
Mount Saint Mary College in Newburgh, NY will be hosting the
Fifth Annual Philosophy Workshop on the theme “Aquinas and the Philosophy of
Nature” from June 4-7. The speakers will
be William Carroll, Fr. James Brent, Alfred Freddoso, Michael Gorman, Jennifer
Frey, Edward Feser, Candace Vogler, John O’Callaghan, and Fr. Michael
Dodds. More information here.
Sunday, January 11, 2015
Post-intentional depression
A reader
asks me to comment on novelist Scott Bakker’s recent Scientia Salon article “Back to Square One: toward a post-intentional
future.” “Intentional” is a reference to intentionality, the philosopher’s
technical term for the meaningfulness or “aboutness” of our thoughts -- the way
they are “directed toward,” “point to,” or are about something. A “post-intentional” future is one in which
we’ve given up trying to explain intentionality in scientific terms and instead
abandon it altogether in favor of radically re-describing human nature exclusively
in terms drawn from neuroscience, physics, chemistry, and the like. In short, it is a future in which we embrace
the eliminative
materialist position associated with philosophers like Alex Rosenberg and
Paul and Patricia Churchland.
Monday, January 5, 2015
Best of 2014
At Catholic World Report, a panel of
contributors lists the
best books they read in 2014. Scholastic
Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction was named by three of them:
Mark Brumley, President and CEO of
Ignatius Press; Christopher Morrissey, Professor of Philosophy at Redeemer
Pacific College (who
reviewed the book in CWR not too long ago); and Fr. James V. Schall,
SJ, Professor Emeritus at Georgetown University. Very kind!
Friday, January 2, 2015
Postscript on plastic
What better
way is there to start off the new year than with another blog post about
plastic? You’ll recall that in a
post from last year, I raised the question of why old plastic -- unlike old
wood, glass, or metal -- seems invariably ugly.
I argued that none of the seemingly obvious answers holds up upon closer
inspection. In particular, I argued that
the “artificiality” of plastic is not the reason, both because there are lots
of old artificial things we don’t find ugly and because there is a sense in
which plastic is not artificial.
Monday, December 29, 2014
Causality, pantheism, and deism
Agere sequitur esse (“action follows being” or “activity follows existence”) is a basic principle of Scholastic metaphysics. The idea is that the way a thing acts or behaves reflects what it is. But suppose that a thing doesn’t truly act or behave at all. Would it not follow, given the principle in question, that it does not truly exist? That would be too quick. After all, a thing might be capable of acting even if it is not in fact doing so. (For example, you are capable of leaving this page and reading some other website instead, even if you do not in fact do so.) That would seem enough to ensure existence. A thing could hardly be said to have a capacity if it didn’t exist. But suppose something lacks even the capacity for acting or behaving. Would it not follow in that case that it does not truly exist?
Friday, December 26, 2014
Martin and Murray on essence and existence
The real distinction between a thing’s essence and its existence is a key Thomistic metaphysical thesis, which I defend at length in Scholastic Metaphysics, at pp. 241-56. The thesis is crucial to Aquinas’s argument for God’s existence in De Ente et Essentia, which is the subject of an eagerly awaited forthcoming book by Gaven Kerr. (HT: Irish Thomist) One well-known argument for the distinction is that you can know thing’s essence without knowing whether or not it exists, in which case its existence must be distinct from its essence. (Again, see Scholastic Metaphysics for defense of this argument.) In his essay “How to Win Essence Back from Essentialists,” David Oderberg suggests that the argument can be run in the other direction as well: “[I]t is possible to know that a thing exists without knowing what kind of thing it is. (Such is our normal way of acquiring knowledge of the world.)” (p. 39)
Which brings
to mind this old Saturday Night Live
skit with Steve Martin and Bill Murray:
Tuesday, December 23, 2014
Christmastime reading for shut-ins
Just
announced: The Institute for Thomistic Philosophy.
At Public Discourse, William Carroll gives
us the scoop on Thomas Aquinas in China.
At Anamnesis, Joshua Hochschild asks: What’s Wrong with Ockham?
Philosopher
Roberto Mangabeira Unger and physicist Lee Smolin have just published The Singular Universe and the Reality of Time:
A Proposal in Natural Philosophy.
In an interview, Smolin addresses the question: Who will rescue
time from the physicists?
Saturday, December 20, 2014
Knowing an ape from Adam
On questions
about biological evolution, both the Magisterium of the Catholic Church and
Thomist philosophers and theologians have tended carefully to steer a middle
course. On the one hand, they have
allowed that a fairly wide range of biological phenomena may in principle be
susceptible of evolutionary explanation, consistent with Catholic doctrine and
Thomistic metaphysics. On the other hand,
they have also insisted, on philosophical and theological grounds, that not every biological phenomenon can be given
an evolutionary explanation, and they refuse to issue a “blank check” to a
purely naturalistic construal of evolution.
Evolutionary explanations are invariably a mixture of empirical and
philosophical considerations. Properly
to be understood, the empirical considerations have to be situated within a
sound metaphysics and philosophy of nature.
Friday, December 12, 2014
Causality and radioactive decay
At the
Catholic blog Vox Nova, mathematics
professor David Cruz-Uribe writes:
I… am currently working through the
metaphysics of St. Thomas Aquinas as part of his proofs of the existence of
God… [S]ome possibly naive counter-examples from quantum mechanics come to
mind. For instance, discussing the principle that nothing can change
without being affected externally, I immediately thought of the spontaneous
decay of atoms and even of particles (e.g., so-called proton decay).
This might be a very naive question:
my knowledge of quantum mechanics is rusty and probably out of date, and I know
much, much less about scholastic metaphysics. So can any of our readers
point me to some useful references on this specific topic?
Friday, December 5, 2014
Working the net
The Daily Beast nominates
Aristotle for a posthumous Nobel prize.
(Even Aristotle’s mistakes are interesting: Next time you see a European
bison, you might not want to stand behind it.
Just in case.)
Physicist
George Ellis, interviewed
at Scientific American,
criticizes Lawrence Krauss, Neil
deGrasse Tyson, and scientism in general. Some choice quotes: “[M]athematical equations
only represent part of reality, and should not be confused with reality,” and “Physicists
should pay attention to Aristotle’s four forms of causation.”
Richard
Bastien kindly
reviews my book Scholastic
Metaphysics in Convivium Magazine. From the review: “Feser’s
refutation [of scientism]… alone makes the purchase of the book well worthwhile.”
Tuesday, December 2, 2014
Progressive dematerialization
In the
Aristotelian-Thomistic (A-T) tradition, it is the intellect, rather than
sentience, that marks the divide between the corporeal and the
incorporeal. Hence A-T arguments against
materialist theories of the mind tend to focus on conceptual thought rather
than qualia (i.e. the subjective or “first-person” features of a conscious
experience, such as the way red looks or the way pain feels) as that aspect of
the mind which cannot in principle be reduced to brain activity or the like. Yet Thomistic writers also often speak even
of perceptual experience (and not just of abstract thought) as involving an
immaterial element. And they need not
deny that qualia-oriented arguments like the “zombie
argument,” Frank Jackson’s “knowledge
argument,” Thomas Nagel’s “bat
argument,” etc. draw blood against materialism. So what exactly is going on here?
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)