From Vice to Kidneys. The Five Drafts commitment device, which more-or-less has succeeded for two vice papers, is now being repositioned for a paper offering a behavioral economics take on compensated live kidney donations. One complication/improvement is that this paper involves a mystery co-author, who will be revealed at a later date!
We seem to be having fewer and fewer drafts.....hmmm. Anyway, I am calling for three drafts for this paper, at least for the version that is scheduled to be presented at a conference. Here's the schedule:
Draft One: Saturday, August 2, 2014
Draft Two: Wednesday, August 20, 2014
Draft Three: Wednesday, September 3, 2014.
The main confounding factor is the looming deadline for my larger project. Oh, but I do want to make a kidney reading commitment. I hope, within one week, to complete reading the very interesting book, The Kidney Sellers, by Sigrid Fry-Revere, concerning the Iranian system(s) of compensated donations; it's been a treat so far.
Here's the current abstract:
Healthy adults are allowed, and even encouraged, to donate a kidney to
patients in dire need of a functional kidney. The encouragement can take
various forms, but under US law (and under the laws of most other
jurisdictions), a kidney donor cannot receive any “valuable
consideration.” The standard contention that informed, rational,
voluntary exchange between adults is mutually (and, absent negative
externalities) socially beneficial does not carry the day with respect
to current public policy towards compensated kidney donations.
Arguments in support of the ban, then, tend to focus on the extent to
which a compensated kidney transfer is informed and voluntary and
rational, and on the possibility of negative externalities. Those
externalities might be of an abstract nature, such as a view that organ
sales are repugnant (Roth, 2007). The wide support that uncompensated
kidney donation receives, however, suggests that considerations of
coercion, poor information, departures from rationality, and negative
externalities are perceived as being more potent in the realm of organ
transactions when valuable consideration is added into the mix.
Departures from rationality in individual decision making are the
central focus of behavioral economics, and hence behavioral economics
has direct applicability to the debate on compensated organ donations.
In Beard and Leitzel (2013), we briefly discussed some behavioral
influences – risk misperceptions, loss aversion, the endowment effect,
and present bias – on the decision to donate a kidney. The goal here is
to broaden and deepen that analysis, and to go beyond donors to look at
behavioral influences on four other sets of actors: patients and
potential patients, family members of patients, organ procurement
agents, and physicians and other medical personnel. How does the
addition of valuable compensation to organ donors influence the
rationality of the decisionmaking of all actors involved in transplants?
How can a compensated system be designed to address the concerns that
are heightened with respect to kidney sales as opposed to uncompensated
donations?
...in which I try to produce a symposium paper on vice policy. Updated for 2014/2015/2016, with new papers, and with fewer drafts!
Tuesday, July 15, 2014
Update on the Four Drafts Paper
Back in early April we posted Draft 3.5a of the handbook chapter on vice regulation. Just wanted to indicate what happened from that point. First, a version nearly identical to Draft 3.5a was sent to the editor of the volume at about the same time that the draft was posted here. A mildly updated version was sent a few weeks later, and that is where things now stand. The editor's initial reaction was rather favorable, so if all goes well, the revisions for the published version will be minimal -- I'll let the devoted Five Drafts reader know about any new developments. But now, I need to set some draft deadlines for another paper....
Monday, April 7, 2014
Draft 3.5(a), Composite
Draft 3.5(a) of Regulating Vice
1.Vice
2. Why Regulate Vice?
3. Surveying the Range of Controls
First half
Second half
4. One Guiding Principle for Vice Regulation
5. Robustly Regulating Casino Gambling
6. Changing Times
7. Vice 3.0
References
1.Vice
2. Why Regulate Vice?
3. Surveying the Range of Controls
First half
Second half
4. One Guiding Principle for Vice Regulation
5. Robustly Regulating Casino Gambling
6. Changing Times
7. Vice 3.0
References
Draft 3.5(a), References
References
Becker, Gary and Kevin Murphy, “A Theory of Rational Addiction.” Journal of Political Economy 96: 675-700, 1988.
Bentham, Jeremy, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. New York: Hafner Press, 1948 [1823].
Bogart, W. A., Permit But Discourage: Regulating Excessive Consumption. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011.
Cook, Philip J., and Michael J. Moore, “The Economics of Alcohol Abuse and Alcohol-Control Policies.” Health Affairs 21(2): 120-133, 2002.
Carpenter, Christopher, and Carlos Dobkin, “The Minimum Legal Drinking Age and Public Health.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 25(2): 133-156, 2011.
Crime in the United States 2012, Federal Bureau of Investigation; available at http://www.fbi.gov/about-us/cjis/ucr/crime-in-the-u.s/2012/crime-in-the-u.s.-2012/persons-arrested/persons-arrested.
Cunningham, Scott, and Todd D. Kendall, “Prostitution 3.0: A Comment.” Iowa Law Review Bulletin 98: 131-141, 2013.
Cunningham, Scott, and Todd D. Kendall, “Prostitution 2.0: The Changing Face of Sex Work.” Journal of Urban Economics 69(3): 273-287, May 2011.
Federal Bureau of Prisons, Inmate Statistics, Offenses; available at http://www.bop.gov/about/statistics/statistics_inmate_offenses.jsp.
Fong, Timothy W., Michael D. Campos, Mary-Lynn Brecht, et al., “Problem and Pathological Gambling in a Sample of Casino Patrons.” Journal of Gambling Studies 27(1): 35-47, March 2011.
Gruber, Jonathan, “The Economics of Tobacco Regulation.” Health Affairs 21(2): 146-162, 2002.
Gruber, Jonathan, and Botond Köszegi, “Is Addiction ‘Rational’? Theory and Evidence.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 116(4): 1261-1303, November 2001.
Holford, T. R., R. Meza, K. E. Warner, et al., “Tobacco Control and the Reduction in Smoking-Related Premature Deaths in the United States, 1964-2012.” Journal of the American Medical Association 311(2): 164-171, 2014.
Kilmer, Beau, and Keith Humphreys, “Losing Your ‘License to Drink’: The Radical South Dakota Approach to Heavy Drinkers Who Threaten Public Safety.” The Brown Journal of World Affairs 20(1): 267-279, Fall/Winter 2013.
Leitzel, Jim, “Toward Drug Control: Exclusion and Buyer Licensing.” Criminal Law and Philosophy 7(1): 99-119, 2013.
Leitzel, Jim, “On Self-exclusion.” Milken Institute Review, 76-81, First Quarter, 2008. Leitzel, Jim, Regulating Vice. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008.
Leitzel, Jim, “Secret Deviants.” Carceral Notebooks 2: 121-125, 2006.
MacAndrew, Craig, and Robert B. Edgerton, Drunken Comportment: A Social Explanation. London: Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1969.
MacCoun, Robert J., and Peter Reuter, Drug War Heresies: Learning from Other Vices, Times, and Places. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Mill, John Stuart, On Liberty, edited by Elizabeth Rapaport. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1978 [1859].
Mill, John Stuart, Principles of Political Economy with some of their Applications to Social Philosophy. William J. Ashley, ed., 1909 [1848]. Library of Economics and Liberty; available at http://www.econlib.org/library/Mill/mlP.html.
Ng, M., M. K. Freeman, T. D. Fleming, et al., “Smoking Prevalence and Cigarette Consumption in 187 Countries, 1980-2012.” Journal of the American Medical Association 311(2): 183-192, 2014.
Nelson, Sarah E., Debi A. LaPlante, Allyson J. Peller, et al., “Real Limits in the Virtual World: Self-Limiting Behavior of Internet Gamblers.” Journal of Gambling Studies 24(4): 463-477, December 2008.
Nutt, David, Drugs Without the Hot Air. Cambridge: UIT Cambridge LTD, 2012.
Peppet, Scott R., “Prostitution 3.0?” Iowa Law Review 98, 2013.
Room, Robin, “Individualised control of drinkers: back to the future?” Contemporary Drug Problems 39(2):311-343, 2012.
Smith, Adam, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, Edwin Cannan, editor. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976 [1776; Cannan edition, 1904].
Spinoza, Benedict de, The Chief Works of Benedict de Spinoza, translated from the Latin, with an Introduction by R.H.M. Elwes, vol. 1 Introduction, Tractatus-Theologico-Politicus, Tractatus Politicus. Revised edition (London: George Bell and Sons, 1891 [1670]). Available from The Online Library of Liberty, at http://oll.libertyfund.org/index.php?option=com_staticxt&staticfile=show.php%3Ftitle=1710&Itemid=27#toc_list
Stutz, Howard, “Singapore casinos produce $6 billion in gaming revenue in 2013; market still trails Las Vegas Strip.” Las Vegas Review-Journal, February 21, 2014.
Thaler, Richard H., and Cass R. Sunstein, Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness. New Haven & London: Yale University Press, 2008.
Thompson, William N., “Handling Corporate Social Responsibility: A Third Way.” Gaming Law Review and Economics 14(5): 355-361, 2010.
Tomkins, S., L. Saburova, N. Kiryanov, et al., “Prevalence and socio-economic distribution of hazardous patterns of alcohol drinking: study of alcohol consumption in men aged 25–54 years in Izhevsk, Russia.” Addiction 102(4): 544-553, 2007.
Weitzer, Ronald, Legalizing Prostitution: From Illicit Vice to Lawful Business. New York University Press, 2012.
WHO Framework Convention on Tobacco Control. World Health Organization, updated 2005; available at www.who.int/fctc/text_download/en/.
Williams, R. J., R. A. Volberg, and R. M. G. Stevens, The Population Prevalence of Problem Gambling: Methodological Influences, Standardized Rates, Jurisdictional Differences, and Worldwide Trends. Report prepared for the Ontario Problem Gambling Research Centre and the Ontario Ministry of Health and Long Term Care, May 8, 2012 available at http://hdl.handle.net/10133/3068.
Zimmerman, M., I. Chelminski, and D. Young, “Prevalence and diagnostic correlates of DSM-IV pathological gambling in psychiatric outpatients.” Journal of Gambling Studies 22: 255-262, 2006.
Zinberg, Norman E., Drug, Set, and Setting: The Basis for Controlled Intoxicant Use. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984.
Becker, Gary and Kevin Murphy, “A Theory of Rational Addiction.” Journal of Political Economy 96: 675-700, 1988.
Bentham, Jeremy, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. New York: Hafner Press, 1948 [1823].
Bogart, W. A., Permit But Discourage: Regulating Excessive Consumption. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011.
Cook, Philip J., and Michael J. Moore, “The Economics of Alcohol Abuse and Alcohol-Control Policies.” Health Affairs 21(2): 120-133, 2002.
Carpenter, Christopher, and Carlos Dobkin, “The Minimum Legal Drinking Age and Public Health.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 25(2): 133-156, 2011.
Crime in the United States 2012, Federal Bureau of Investigation; available at http://www.fbi.gov/about-us/cjis/ucr/crime-in-the-u.s/2012/crime-in-the-u.s.-2012/persons-arrested/persons-arrested.
Cunningham, Scott, and Todd D. Kendall, “Prostitution 3.0: A Comment.” Iowa Law Review Bulletin 98: 131-141, 2013.
Cunningham, Scott, and Todd D. Kendall, “Prostitution 2.0: The Changing Face of Sex Work.” Journal of Urban Economics 69(3): 273-287, May 2011.
Federal Bureau of Prisons, Inmate Statistics, Offenses; available at http://www.bop.gov/about/statistics/statistics_inmate_offenses.jsp.
Fong, Timothy W., Michael D. Campos, Mary-Lynn Brecht, et al., “Problem and Pathological Gambling in a Sample of Casino Patrons.” Journal of Gambling Studies 27(1): 35-47, March 2011.
Gruber, Jonathan, “The Economics of Tobacco Regulation.” Health Affairs 21(2): 146-162, 2002.
Gruber, Jonathan, and Botond Köszegi, “Is Addiction ‘Rational’? Theory and Evidence.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 116(4): 1261-1303, November 2001.
Holford, T. R., R. Meza, K. E. Warner, et al., “Tobacco Control and the Reduction in Smoking-Related Premature Deaths in the United States, 1964-2012.” Journal of the American Medical Association 311(2): 164-171, 2014.
Kilmer, Beau, and Keith Humphreys, “Losing Your ‘License to Drink’: The Radical South Dakota Approach to Heavy Drinkers Who Threaten Public Safety.” The Brown Journal of World Affairs 20(1): 267-279, Fall/Winter 2013.
Leitzel, Jim, “Toward Drug Control: Exclusion and Buyer Licensing.” Criminal Law and Philosophy 7(1): 99-119, 2013.
Leitzel, Jim, “On Self-exclusion.” Milken Institute Review, 76-81, First Quarter, 2008. Leitzel, Jim, Regulating Vice. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008.
Leitzel, Jim, “Secret Deviants.” Carceral Notebooks 2: 121-125, 2006.
MacAndrew, Craig, and Robert B. Edgerton, Drunken Comportment: A Social Explanation. London: Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1969.
MacCoun, Robert J., and Peter Reuter, Drug War Heresies: Learning from Other Vices, Times, and Places. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Mill, John Stuart, On Liberty, edited by Elizabeth Rapaport. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1978 [1859].
Mill, John Stuart, Principles of Political Economy with some of their Applications to Social Philosophy. William J. Ashley, ed., 1909 [1848]. Library of Economics and Liberty; available at http://www.econlib.org/library/Mill/mlP.html.
Ng, M., M. K. Freeman, T. D. Fleming, et al., “Smoking Prevalence and Cigarette Consumption in 187 Countries, 1980-2012.” Journal of the American Medical Association 311(2): 183-192, 2014.
Nelson, Sarah E., Debi A. LaPlante, Allyson J. Peller, et al., “Real Limits in the Virtual World: Self-Limiting Behavior of Internet Gamblers.” Journal of Gambling Studies 24(4): 463-477, December 2008.
Nutt, David, Drugs Without the Hot Air. Cambridge: UIT Cambridge LTD, 2012.
Peppet, Scott R., “Prostitution 3.0?” Iowa Law Review 98, 2013.
Room, Robin, “Individualised control of drinkers: back to the future?” Contemporary Drug Problems 39(2):311-343, 2012.
Smith, Adam, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, Edwin Cannan, editor. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976 [1776; Cannan edition, 1904].
Spinoza, Benedict de, The Chief Works of Benedict de Spinoza, translated from the Latin, with an Introduction by R.H.M. Elwes, vol. 1 Introduction, Tractatus-Theologico-Politicus, Tractatus Politicus. Revised edition (London: George Bell and Sons, 1891 [1670]). Available from The Online Library of Liberty, at http://oll.libertyfund.org/index.php?option=com_staticxt&staticfile=show.php%3Ftitle=1710&Itemid=27#toc_list
Stutz, Howard, “Singapore casinos produce $6 billion in gaming revenue in 2013; market still trails Las Vegas Strip.” Las Vegas Review-Journal, February 21, 2014.
Thaler, Richard H., and Cass R. Sunstein, Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness. New Haven & London: Yale University Press, 2008.
Thompson, William N., “Handling Corporate Social Responsibility: A Third Way.” Gaming Law Review and Economics 14(5): 355-361, 2010.
Tomkins, S., L. Saburova, N. Kiryanov, et al., “Prevalence and socio-economic distribution of hazardous patterns of alcohol drinking: study of alcohol consumption in men aged 25–54 years in Izhevsk, Russia.” Addiction 102(4): 544-553, 2007.
Weitzer, Ronald, Legalizing Prostitution: From Illicit Vice to Lawful Business. New York University Press, 2012.
WHO Framework Convention on Tobacco Control. World Health Organization, updated 2005; available at www.who.int/fctc/text_download/en/.
Williams, R. J., R. A. Volberg, and R. M. G. Stevens, The Population Prevalence of Problem Gambling: Methodological Influences, Standardized Rates, Jurisdictional Differences, and Worldwide Trends. Report prepared for the Ontario Problem Gambling Research Centre and the Ontario Ministry of Health and Long Term Care, May 8, 2012 available at http://hdl.handle.net/10133/3068.
Zimmerman, M., I. Chelminski, and D. Young, “Prevalence and diagnostic correlates of DSM-IV pathological gambling in psychiatric outpatients.” Journal of Gambling Studies 22: 255-262, 2006.
Zinberg, Norman E., Drug, Set, and Setting: The Basis for Controlled Intoxicant Use. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984.
Draft 3.5(a), Section 7
7. Vice 3.0
It is a commonplace to note that the internet has changed everything, and this trope would apply to vice regulation, too. Then again, vice has changed the internet: pornography, gambling, prostitution, and prescription pharmaceuticals have been major elements of web commerce almost since the internet’s inception, and have helped to push forward internet technology, including web video quality, anonymity protections, and age verification. But the direction of influence that moves from the internet to vice is, if anything, more profound, and holds the potential to drive future policy regimes.
In the case of pornography and gambling, the internet has allowed “consumption” to take place in the privacy and comfort of one’s home, instead of in a public theatre or casino, say. This privatization of consumption represents a vast expansion in the availability of these vices. Often the existing regulatory structure pre-supposes or enforces a certain level of availability and a specific mode of consumption. Regulations aimed at bricks-and-mortar casinos or strip clubs might not extend to internet gambling or webcam porn, leaving these types of online vice initially unregulated. Simultaneously, the external costs associated with vice consumption can be reduced via private consumption; public nuisance problems or streetwalking in the area of a triple-x theatre do not have obvious parallels with internet porn.
At-home participation also goes a long way to eliminate some of the non-monetary “costs” of consuming vice, such as the potential for embarrassment when seen walking into an adult book store or cinema, or when transacting with the clerks in such establishments. Prescription pharmaceuticals such as Viagra might be purchasable over the internet without an initial in-person consultation with a physician. Payments for internet vice might be shielded from the view of family members, too, through the use of PayPal or Bitcoins. Greater availability and lower costs suggest the possibility of considerable increases in consumption and perhaps compulsive behavior. Surely internet pornography and gambling have led to addictive conduct among many people who were not at much risk of a non-virtual porn or betting addiction; video games and the internet in general have sparked their own digital addictions (though perhaps these have served as a substitute for alcohol consumption or other vices that are less salubrious).
The internet has revolutionized what might be termed the supply sides of pornography and prostitution. Aspiring porn actors now need not travel to southern California; rather, they can produce – and distribute globally – pornography from their own homes. Escorts can advertise on the web, easing the task of making a connection with clients, and also use the internet to verify potential clients’ identities, reputations, and credit cards. Internet-based sex work is by no means a perfectly safe endeavor, but it involves much lower risks than streetwalking, and is perhaps safer still in areas where prostitution itself is legal (Weitzer 2012). Where prostitution is illegal, web publicity not only allows connections to be made, it allows law enforcers to track sellers, too. Nonetheless, the overall impact of the web seems to be, so far, on the side of diminishing the arrest risks for prostitutes (Cunningham and Kendall, 2011).
Along with a degree of anonymity, the web offers the ability to selectively undo that anonymity. Those with an interest in legal, consensual behaviors – behaviors that people might not want to openly disclose to the world – can make good use of the internet, then. People who would like to explore sado-masochistic sexual practices, for instance, can make connections over the internet in a relatively safe manner (Leitzel 2008b). They can learn about S&M, purchase books and equipment, and reveal their own experiences and fantasies. The internet has proved to be a huge boon to poker, as players can easily be brought together via the web nexus, and novice players needn’t fear face-to-face embarrassment from poor play, while honing their skills at low or even zero stakes.
Vice researchers, policymakers, and the public at large also can be educated via the internet. To the extent that it is unfamiliarity that stokes fear and suspicions of immorality, the internet holds the potential to broaden minds and liberalize the attitudes and laws that currently are arrayed against seemingly immoral vices. As always, however, the vice-related internet is doubled-edged, and depictions of odd or alarming behavior by vice participants can go viral on the web – this happened in the US in the case of the drug mephedrone (“bath salts”), which was banned in 2011 – and induce those moral panics that often drive repressive legislation. (Moral panics are not an exclusively digital phenomenon, of course; regulatory action against mephedrone in the UK was stimulated by various mistaken newspaper reports of horrific outcomes for some young people suspected of using the drug (Nutt, 2012).) The intended “selective disclosure” of sexting or social media photos of drinking or drug taking has proven to be insufficiently selective at times, with indiscretions becoming widely publicized and available to almost anyone, including future employers.
Beyond offering much greater availability to vice, the internet eases the access to treatment resources: people can be just as shy about seeking treatment as they are about publicly indulging in vice, so options to contact treatment providers over the internet can be helpful. Web-based casinos can be required to provide links to treatment providers, as well as highlight opportunities to self-exclude or self-limit.
The internet can go beyond reducing information and transaction costs and enhancing privacy; rather, it can facilitate a wholesale transformation in the nature of commercial vice, something akin to how the internet and digitization revolutionized “games”. Prostitutes and their clients, for instance, could be thoroughly vetted for disease, trustworthiness, financial solvency, and safety, even while protecting their anonymity, through internet intermediaries that collect and verify information on STD tests, credit histories, and criminal backgrounds, for instance, and allow both the buyer and seller access to that information before their encounter. (This scenario is developed more fully in Peppet (2013).) The harms associated with prostitution thereby might be greatly diminished. Personalized drugs might be designed and purchased via the web, or fabricated at home from web-acquired directions on 3D printers.
In terms of the robustness approach to vice regulation, the internet, on balance, and for the time being, seems to be helpful. Vice consumption choices are better informed, with the dangers of vices and the effects, many of them unintended and negative, connected with regulations made clearer. Those repressive regulatory regimes that are furthest from meeting the robustness principle, especially drug prohibition, are eased somewhat, and have their harms reduced, by the de facto web-based liberalization (Pepett, 2013; Cunningham and Kendall, 2013). This liberalization might make it still more evident that vice cannot be abolished – at least at any tolerable cost – and illustrate Spinoza’s wisdom, that “It is best to grant what cannot be abolished, even though it be in itself harmful.”
It is a commonplace to note that the internet has changed everything, and this trope would apply to vice regulation, too. Then again, vice has changed the internet: pornography, gambling, prostitution, and prescription pharmaceuticals have been major elements of web commerce almost since the internet’s inception, and have helped to push forward internet technology, including web video quality, anonymity protections, and age verification. But the direction of influence that moves from the internet to vice is, if anything, more profound, and holds the potential to drive future policy regimes.
In the case of pornography and gambling, the internet has allowed “consumption” to take place in the privacy and comfort of one’s home, instead of in a public theatre or casino, say. This privatization of consumption represents a vast expansion in the availability of these vices. Often the existing regulatory structure pre-supposes or enforces a certain level of availability and a specific mode of consumption. Regulations aimed at bricks-and-mortar casinos or strip clubs might not extend to internet gambling or webcam porn, leaving these types of online vice initially unregulated. Simultaneously, the external costs associated with vice consumption can be reduced via private consumption; public nuisance problems or streetwalking in the area of a triple-x theatre do not have obvious parallels with internet porn.
At-home participation also goes a long way to eliminate some of the non-monetary “costs” of consuming vice, such as the potential for embarrassment when seen walking into an adult book store or cinema, or when transacting with the clerks in such establishments. Prescription pharmaceuticals such as Viagra might be purchasable over the internet without an initial in-person consultation with a physician. Payments for internet vice might be shielded from the view of family members, too, through the use of PayPal or Bitcoins. Greater availability and lower costs suggest the possibility of considerable increases in consumption and perhaps compulsive behavior. Surely internet pornography and gambling have led to addictive conduct among many people who were not at much risk of a non-virtual porn or betting addiction; video games and the internet in general have sparked their own digital addictions (though perhaps these have served as a substitute for alcohol consumption or other vices that are less salubrious).
The internet has revolutionized what might be termed the supply sides of pornography and prostitution. Aspiring porn actors now need not travel to southern California; rather, they can produce – and distribute globally – pornography from their own homes. Escorts can advertise on the web, easing the task of making a connection with clients, and also use the internet to verify potential clients’ identities, reputations, and credit cards. Internet-based sex work is by no means a perfectly safe endeavor, but it involves much lower risks than streetwalking, and is perhaps safer still in areas where prostitution itself is legal (Weitzer 2012). Where prostitution is illegal, web publicity not only allows connections to be made, it allows law enforcers to track sellers, too. Nonetheless, the overall impact of the web seems to be, so far, on the side of diminishing the arrest risks for prostitutes (Cunningham and Kendall, 2011).
Along with a degree of anonymity, the web offers the ability to selectively undo that anonymity. Those with an interest in legal, consensual behaviors – behaviors that people might not want to openly disclose to the world – can make good use of the internet, then. People who would like to explore sado-masochistic sexual practices, for instance, can make connections over the internet in a relatively safe manner (Leitzel 2008b). They can learn about S&M, purchase books and equipment, and reveal their own experiences and fantasies. The internet has proved to be a huge boon to poker, as players can easily be brought together via the web nexus, and novice players needn’t fear face-to-face embarrassment from poor play, while honing their skills at low or even zero stakes.
Vice researchers, policymakers, and the public at large also can be educated via the internet. To the extent that it is unfamiliarity that stokes fear and suspicions of immorality, the internet holds the potential to broaden minds and liberalize the attitudes and laws that currently are arrayed against seemingly immoral vices. As always, however, the vice-related internet is doubled-edged, and depictions of odd or alarming behavior by vice participants can go viral on the web – this happened in the US in the case of the drug mephedrone (“bath salts”), which was banned in 2011 – and induce those moral panics that often drive repressive legislation. (Moral panics are not an exclusively digital phenomenon, of course; regulatory action against mephedrone in the UK was stimulated by various mistaken newspaper reports of horrific outcomes for some young people suspected of using the drug (Nutt, 2012).) The intended “selective disclosure” of sexting or social media photos of drinking or drug taking has proven to be insufficiently selective at times, with indiscretions becoming widely publicized and available to almost anyone, including future employers.
Beyond offering much greater availability to vice, the internet eases the access to treatment resources: people can be just as shy about seeking treatment as they are about publicly indulging in vice, so options to contact treatment providers over the internet can be helpful. Web-based casinos can be required to provide links to treatment providers, as well as highlight opportunities to self-exclude or self-limit.
The internet can go beyond reducing information and transaction costs and enhancing privacy; rather, it can facilitate a wholesale transformation in the nature of commercial vice, something akin to how the internet and digitization revolutionized “games”. Prostitutes and their clients, for instance, could be thoroughly vetted for disease, trustworthiness, financial solvency, and safety, even while protecting their anonymity, through internet intermediaries that collect and verify information on STD tests, credit histories, and criminal backgrounds, for instance, and allow both the buyer and seller access to that information before their encounter. (This scenario is developed more fully in Peppet (2013).) The harms associated with prostitution thereby might be greatly diminished. Personalized drugs might be designed and purchased via the web, or fabricated at home from web-acquired directions on 3D printers.
In terms of the robustness approach to vice regulation, the internet, on balance, and for the time being, seems to be helpful. Vice consumption choices are better informed, with the dangers of vices and the effects, many of them unintended and negative, connected with regulations made clearer. Those repressive regulatory regimes that are furthest from meeting the robustness principle, especially drug prohibition, are eased somewhat, and have their harms reduced, by the de facto web-based liberalization (Pepett, 2013; Cunningham and Kendall, 2013). This liberalization might make it still more evident that vice cannot be abolished – at least at any tolerable cost – and illustrate Spinoza’s wisdom, that “It is best to grant what cannot be abolished, even though it be in itself harmful.”
Draft 3.5(a), Section Six
6. Changing Times
The absence of significant harms-to-others from vice lends an instability to vice policy. If burdens or punishments cannot be calibrated against the harm of an act to society, fads and moral panics tend to fill the vacuum. At any rate, vice regulation demonstrates tremendous variation over time and place, with specific vices sometimes banned, and at other times made widely available and all-but-lauded. Some of the recent trends will be outlined here.
(1) Tobacco The regulatory approach to tobacco, and particularly towards cigarettes, has become much stricter in recent decades. The tightening of restrictions on tobacco is a global phenomenon. The World Health Organization’s Framework Convention on Tobacco Control came into force in 2005, and has been joined by more than 175 nations. The Convention commits countries to an array of measures, including taxes and advertising controls, aimed at reducing tobacco consumption. In the US (which signed but never ratified the WHO Convention), higher taxes and diminished availability of vending machine outlets for cigarettes are two notable changes of the past twenty years, but perhaps most telling is the severe reduction in legal places to smoke in public. A trend that started with bans on smoking in airplanes and hospitals, has, in the US as in much of the world, spread to most workplaces, restaurants, and even pubs. In the US, the percentage of adults who smoke has fallen from over 40% in the mid-1960s to about 18 percent in recent years – a smoking rate that is near the global average (Holford, Meza, Warner, et al., 2014; Ng, Freeman, Fleming, et al., 2014). We have come a long way (baby), from the World War I and World War II eras, when cigarettes were included in the rations provided to soldiers and prisoners of war.
(2) Marijuana Marijuana has been globally prohibited (and covered by the UN conventions on drugs that promote worldwide prohibition) for many decades now, but the once near-consensus that a ban (usually extended to possession as well as purchase, sale, manufacture, and transport) is desirable has shown significant cracks. (The three UN drug treaties can be accessed at http://www.unodc.org/unodc/en/treaties/index.html?ref=menuside.) Initial forays have included the legalization of marijuana for medical purposes, a change that has occurred in 20 US states and the District of Columbia. (Marijuana, medical or otherwise, remains prohibited at the federal level in the United States.) Uruguay has legalized marijuana for recreational use, too, as have two US states, Colorado and Washington. Many countries and US states have adopted decriminalization or depenalization reforms that generally preclude any sort of serious punishment for marijuana users, though sellers might still be arrested and receive significant jail time.
(3) War on Drugs Marijuana is one of the more benign of the currently illegal drugs, and also the most popular. These factors, perhaps combined with pot’s obvious ability to offer relief to some patients in medical distress, help to explain why marijuana is the drug for which global prohibition is proving least sustainable. Nonetheless, the entire edifice of a prohibitory stance towards recreational drugs also has begun to crumble, probably due to the horrific consequences of the war on drugs. Portugal, the Czech Republic, the Netherlands, Mexico, Argentina, Uruguay, and some other countries have adopted fairly broad depenalization plans for personal use, and addiction is treated in many countries as a health problem, not a criminal justice concern. Still, much of the world, including Malaysia, Singapore, China, Vietnam, Indonesia, and Iran, among other nations, enforces draconian penalties against those deemed to be in the illicit drug trade – and possession of rather small amounts of drugs is viewed as per se evidence as involvement in the trade.
(4) Gambling The last half century has witnessed a significant global liberalization of gambling regulations. Since 1960, the number of US states hosting legal casinos (including Native American casinos) has gone from one to more than 30, and the number of states offering lotteries has climbed from zero to more than 40. Asia recently has become a world casino powerhouse: gambling revenues in Macau are much higher than in any other casino locale, while Singapore’s two casinos have combined revenues from gambling that are about the same as that generated by the dozens of casinos in Las Vegas (Stutz, 2014).
One hopeful lesson from the expansion of global gambling opportunities is that this expansion has not been accompanied by a significant long-term increase in the proportion of the population facing serious gambling problems; nonetheless, in the shorter-term, there is evidence that problem gambling tends to rise with gambling availability (Williams, Volberg, and Stevens, 2012). One possible explanation of the differing short and long-term impacts is that with time, the novelty of easily accessible gambling dissipates, while some problem gamblers are able to adapt to abstinence or a more recreational style of play. [Adam Smith (1776, p. 518) noted such a pattern with respect to an increased availability of alcohol: “When a French regiment comes from some of the northern provinces of France, where wine is somewhat dear, to be quartered in the southern, where it is very cheap, the soldiers, I have frequently heard it observed, are at first debauched by the cheapness and novelty of good wine; but after a few months residence, the greater part of them become as sober as the rest of the inhabitants.”]
(5) Prostitution While tobacco has become more tightly regulated in recent decades, the trend for marijuana and other drugs, and in gambling, has been towards liberalization. Prostitution is harder to characterize on a leniency scale, as the world has been splitting between opposite approaches, one that accepts some forms of legal, regulated prostitution, and another that shifts the focus on the traditional ban from prostitutes to their customers. In much of the world, prostitution is illegal, though in some places where it is criminalized – including Thailand – it is tolerated, while in other locales it is severely punished. In Britain and Canada, prostitution per se is legal, though related activities, such a streetwalking or keeping a brothel, are illegal. Brothel prostitution is legal in many countries, including Germany and Switzerland, as well as in some Australian states. New Zealand has perhaps the most liberal rules governing prostitution: consensual agreements between adults for paid sex are legal, as are related activities, including streetwalking. The alternative approach of one-sided enforcement, where sellers are not breaking the law but buyers are, was instituted in Sweden in 1999, subsequently adopted in Iceland and Norway, and continues to be influential in prostitution policy debates.
The absence of significant harms-to-others from vice lends an instability to vice policy. If burdens or punishments cannot be calibrated against the harm of an act to society, fads and moral panics tend to fill the vacuum. At any rate, vice regulation demonstrates tremendous variation over time and place, with specific vices sometimes banned, and at other times made widely available and all-but-lauded. Some of the recent trends will be outlined here.
(1) Tobacco The regulatory approach to tobacco, and particularly towards cigarettes, has become much stricter in recent decades. The tightening of restrictions on tobacco is a global phenomenon. The World Health Organization’s Framework Convention on Tobacco Control came into force in 2005, and has been joined by more than 175 nations. The Convention commits countries to an array of measures, including taxes and advertising controls, aimed at reducing tobacco consumption. In the US (which signed but never ratified the WHO Convention), higher taxes and diminished availability of vending machine outlets for cigarettes are two notable changes of the past twenty years, but perhaps most telling is the severe reduction in legal places to smoke in public. A trend that started with bans on smoking in airplanes and hospitals, has, in the US as in much of the world, spread to most workplaces, restaurants, and even pubs. In the US, the percentage of adults who smoke has fallen from over 40% in the mid-1960s to about 18 percent in recent years – a smoking rate that is near the global average (Holford, Meza, Warner, et al., 2014; Ng, Freeman, Fleming, et al., 2014). We have come a long way (baby), from the World War I and World War II eras, when cigarettes were included in the rations provided to soldiers and prisoners of war.
(2) Marijuana Marijuana has been globally prohibited (and covered by the UN conventions on drugs that promote worldwide prohibition) for many decades now, but the once near-consensus that a ban (usually extended to possession as well as purchase, sale, manufacture, and transport) is desirable has shown significant cracks. (The three UN drug treaties can be accessed at http://www.unodc.org/unodc/en/treaties/index.html?ref=menuside.) Initial forays have included the legalization of marijuana for medical purposes, a change that has occurred in 20 US states and the District of Columbia. (Marijuana, medical or otherwise, remains prohibited at the federal level in the United States.) Uruguay has legalized marijuana for recreational use, too, as have two US states, Colorado and Washington. Many countries and US states have adopted decriminalization or depenalization reforms that generally preclude any sort of serious punishment for marijuana users, though sellers might still be arrested and receive significant jail time.
(3) War on Drugs Marijuana is one of the more benign of the currently illegal drugs, and also the most popular. These factors, perhaps combined with pot’s obvious ability to offer relief to some patients in medical distress, help to explain why marijuana is the drug for which global prohibition is proving least sustainable. Nonetheless, the entire edifice of a prohibitory stance towards recreational drugs also has begun to crumble, probably due to the horrific consequences of the war on drugs. Portugal, the Czech Republic, the Netherlands, Mexico, Argentina, Uruguay, and some other countries have adopted fairly broad depenalization plans for personal use, and addiction is treated in many countries as a health problem, not a criminal justice concern. Still, much of the world, including Malaysia, Singapore, China, Vietnam, Indonesia, and Iran, among other nations, enforces draconian penalties against those deemed to be in the illicit drug trade – and possession of rather small amounts of drugs is viewed as per se evidence as involvement in the trade.
(4) Gambling The last half century has witnessed a significant global liberalization of gambling regulations. Since 1960, the number of US states hosting legal casinos (including Native American casinos) has gone from one to more than 30, and the number of states offering lotteries has climbed from zero to more than 40. Asia recently has become a world casino powerhouse: gambling revenues in Macau are much higher than in any other casino locale, while Singapore’s two casinos have combined revenues from gambling that are about the same as that generated by the dozens of casinos in Las Vegas (Stutz, 2014).
One hopeful lesson from the expansion of global gambling opportunities is that this expansion has not been accompanied by a significant long-term increase in the proportion of the population facing serious gambling problems; nonetheless, in the shorter-term, there is evidence that problem gambling tends to rise with gambling availability (Williams, Volberg, and Stevens, 2012). One possible explanation of the differing short and long-term impacts is that with time, the novelty of easily accessible gambling dissipates, while some problem gamblers are able to adapt to abstinence or a more recreational style of play. [Adam Smith (1776, p. 518) noted such a pattern with respect to an increased availability of alcohol: “When a French regiment comes from some of the northern provinces of France, where wine is somewhat dear, to be quartered in the southern, where it is very cheap, the soldiers, I have frequently heard it observed, are at first debauched by the cheapness and novelty of good wine; but after a few months residence, the greater part of them become as sober as the rest of the inhabitants.”]
(5) Prostitution While tobacco has become more tightly regulated in recent decades, the trend for marijuana and other drugs, and in gambling, has been towards liberalization. Prostitution is harder to characterize on a leniency scale, as the world has been splitting between opposite approaches, one that accepts some forms of legal, regulated prostitution, and another that shifts the focus on the traditional ban from prostitutes to their customers. In much of the world, prostitution is illegal, though in some places where it is criminalized – including Thailand – it is tolerated, while in other locales it is severely punished. In Britain and Canada, prostitution per se is legal, though related activities, such a streetwalking or keeping a brothel, are illegal. Brothel prostitution is legal in many countries, including Germany and Switzerland, as well as in some Australian states. New Zealand has perhaps the most liberal rules governing prostitution: consensual agreements between adults for paid sex are legal, as are related activities, including streetwalking. The alternative approach of one-sided enforcement, where sellers are not breaking the law but buyers are, was instituted in Sweden in 1999, subsequently adopted in Iceland and Norway, and continues to be influential in prostitution policy debates.
Draft 3.5(a), Section Five
5. Robustly Regulating Casino Gambling
The robustness principle, like Mill’s harm principle, suggests that gambling should be legal. As it would be difficult for people to gamble in a safe manner without gambling providers, “sales” of gambling services also must be legal. Casinos are the standard method of providing such services, though lotteries (the most popular form of gambling) generally operate in a separate system outside of casinos.
Robustness requires that the regulatory regime lead to acceptable outcomes even when many gamblers are addicted or misinformed or irrational with respect to their wagering behavior. These rationality shortfalls are not just theoretical in the case of gambling; rather, they are pervasive. Something on the order of two percent of the adult population typically falls within the clinical understanding of disordered gambling – though the percentage of casino patrons who are problem gamblers is much higher (Fong, Campos, Brecht, et al., 2011). These individuals suffer enormous costs stemming from their gambling fixation, including family breakdown, bankruptcy, and job loss. But even non-problem gamblers often misunderstand probabilities of winning and losing, and selectively forget past losses relative to wins, so that their views of their own gambling outcomes are quite skewed. Gamblers hold unreasonable beliefs about past play influencing future outcomes, such as the notion that a particular slot machine is “hot”: they believe (incorrectly) that a hot machine temporarily offers better winning prospects.
Countering incorrect beliefs is an important component of any robust gambling policy. Clear and prominent identification of the odds of winning (or perhaps of losing) could be mandated. One of the more startling facts about electronic gambling machines is that players are very poorly informed about the average “price” of a play. Regulations generally require slot machines to pay out some minimum percentage of their takings, such as 80%. A machine that costs $1 per play, and just met such a regulatory standard, therefore would have an average net price of 20 cents per play. But the machine might be set for an average return of 98% of the wagers, leaving an average net price of 2 cents per play. Gamblers are not informed of the average net price of a play, however, even though it can vary by an order of magnitude across different machines (or on the same machine over time). Imagine going to the store and buying a loaf of bread, and not knowing until you bought it whether it cost $1 or $10. And in the case of the slot machines, unless you play for many, many hours, you can’t be confident of the average net price even after you make your purchases. A mandate to provide clear pricing information would seem to be an all but necessary element of a robust casino regulatory regime.
Price information might be presented in easy to understand ways, including the “average net price per play,” as described above. In addition, for instance, the expected loss per $100 wagered could be given. (Today’s networked, progressive slots imply that the expectation changes over time, but second-by-second updating is easy to electronically compute and display. The potential to play multiple lines on a slot machine also muddies the picture, but again, not in such a way that prices of different gambler options can’t be determined and displayed.) Other information that could continuously be on offer might be the amount of money wagered in a given session, the current net loss position, and the amount of time spent gambling. (Problem gamblers not only suffer from money woes, they also end up spending very significant amounts of time gambling, to the detriment of other dimensions of their lives; see, e.g., Nelson, LaPlante, Peller, et al., 2008). The electronic cards that most regular gamblers use as part of casino loyalty programs also can be used to gather and disseminate this information.
Self-limit and self-exclusion programs should also be part of a robust gambling regulatory regime. A self-limit program allows gamblers to pre-commit as to how much money they are willing to lose prior to a gambling session. (The relevant timeframe could be longer, too, such as limiting losses per month or per year, or limits could be set across multiple timeframes.) The limit is irrevocable, so that in-the-moment passions cannot override judgments made earlier and (hopefully) in a more considered fashion. It would also be compatible with a robust regime to require every patron to choose a binding loss limit upon entering a casino – a policy Australia has considered implementing – as such a policy can do much to limit the harms of gambling, while imposing very little on rational bettors, who, like everyone, would be allowed to choose a very high limit if that is their pre-gambling preference.
Self-exclusion programs are an extreme form of voluntary self-limit, in that the limit is set to zero. Generally gamblers who choose to self-exclude are not allowed admission to a casino, and can be charged with trespassing should they attempt to breach their agreement. Administration is less than perfect, but enforcement can be aided through technological means such as facial recognition software, or by requiring that all casino patrons present identification upon entering. (The imposition of an ID requirement on non-excluded gamblers is sufficiently minimal that it would not violate robustness, and in any event, ID checks often are necessary to enforce age restrictions.) Jurisdictions typically offer multiple options when self-excluders choose the duration of their ban; some exclusion agreements are in effect for as little as 6 months, while others go to five years and beyond.
A self-exclusion program allows gamblers to opt out, while offering more commitment to that choice than comes from most declarations of abstinence. (Individuals might be able to sign private commitment contracts that also raise the stakes of breaching a no-gambling pledge, and hence potentially provide more motivation to abstain, too; see stickk.com.) Further, the self-exclusion system operates in a fashion that is all but invisible to those satisfied gamblers who choose not to opt out. (A common shortcoming of self-exclusion programs is that they are invisible to problem gamblers, too, in the sense that many regular casino patrons do not know about the existence of self-exclusion schemes.) A more forceful version of an exclusion regime is to alter the default setting so that exclusion is the starting point: adults who want to gamble must opt-in, must take some positive steps to acquire a “license” to gamble. Those positive steps might be quite minor, such as a few days delay between the moment that a license (or “membership” in a casino, perhaps) is applied for and when the license is granted – this was a longtime British casino regulation – or something more involved, including passing an exam indicating that the applicant possesses a basic understanding of probabilities and the likelihood of monetary loss from casino gambling. People who choose not to take the requisite positive steps, then, are thereby self-excluded.
The robustness principle, like Mill’s harm principle, suggests that gambling should be legal. As it would be difficult for people to gamble in a safe manner without gambling providers, “sales” of gambling services also must be legal. Casinos are the standard method of providing such services, though lotteries (the most popular form of gambling) generally operate in a separate system outside of casinos.
Robustness requires that the regulatory regime lead to acceptable outcomes even when many gamblers are addicted or misinformed or irrational with respect to their wagering behavior. These rationality shortfalls are not just theoretical in the case of gambling; rather, they are pervasive. Something on the order of two percent of the adult population typically falls within the clinical understanding of disordered gambling – though the percentage of casino patrons who are problem gamblers is much higher (Fong, Campos, Brecht, et al., 2011). These individuals suffer enormous costs stemming from their gambling fixation, including family breakdown, bankruptcy, and job loss. But even non-problem gamblers often misunderstand probabilities of winning and losing, and selectively forget past losses relative to wins, so that their views of their own gambling outcomes are quite skewed. Gamblers hold unreasonable beliefs about past play influencing future outcomes, such as the notion that a particular slot machine is “hot”: they believe (incorrectly) that a hot machine temporarily offers better winning prospects.
Countering incorrect beliefs is an important component of any robust gambling policy. Clear and prominent identification of the odds of winning (or perhaps of losing) could be mandated. One of the more startling facts about electronic gambling machines is that players are very poorly informed about the average “price” of a play. Regulations generally require slot machines to pay out some minimum percentage of their takings, such as 80%. A machine that costs $1 per play, and just met such a regulatory standard, therefore would have an average net price of 20 cents per play. But the machine might be set for an average return of 98% of the wagers, leaving an average net price of 2 cents per play. Gamblers are not informed of the average net price of a play, however, even though it can vary by an order of magnitude across different machines (or on the same machine over time). Imagine going to the store and buying a loaf of bread, and not knowing until you bought it whether it cost $1 or $10. And in the case of the slot machines, unless you play for many, many hours, you can’t be confident of the average net price even after you make your purchases. A mandate to provide clear pricing information would seem to be an all but necessary element of a robust casino regulatory regime.
Price information might be presented in easy to understand ways, including the “average net price per play,” as described above. In addition, for instance, the expected loss per $100 wagered could be given. (Today’s networked, progressive slots imply that the expectation changes over time, but second-by-second updating is easy to electronically compute and display. The potential to play multiple lines on a slot machine also muddies the picture, but again, not in such a way that prices of different gambler options can’t be determined and displayed.) Other information that could continuously be on offer might be the amount of money wagered in a given session, the current net loss position, and the amount of time spent gambling. (Problem gamblers not only suffer from money woes, they also end up spending very significant amounts of time gambling, to the detriment of other dimensions of their lives; see, e.g., Nelson, LaPlante, Peller, et al., 2008). The electronic cards that most regular gamblers use as part of casino loyalty programs also can be used to gather and disseminate this information.
Self-limit and self-exclusion programs should also be part of a robust gambling regulatory regime. A self-limit program allows gamblers to pre-commit as to how much money they are willing to lose prior to a gambling session. (The relevant timeframe could be longer, too, such as limiting losses per month or per year, or limits could be set across multiple timeframes.) The limit is irrevocable, so that in-the-moment passions cannot override judgments made earlier and (hopefully) in a more considered fashion. It would also be compatible with a robust regime to require every patron to choose a binding loss limit upon entering a casino – a policy Australia has considered implementing – as such a policy can do much to limit the harms of gambling, while imposing very little on rational bettors, who, like everyone, would be allowed to choose a very high limit if that is their pre-gambling preference.
Self-exclusion programs are an extreme form of voluntary self-limit, in that the limit is set to zero. Generally gamblers who choose to self-exclude are not allowed admission to a casino, and can be charged with trespassing should they attempt to breach their agreement. Administration is less than perfect, but enforcement can be aided through technological means such as facial recognition software, or by requiring that all casino patrons present identification upon entering. (The imposition of an ID requirement on non-excluded gamblers is sufficiently minimal that it would not violate robustness, and in any event, ID checks often are necessary to enforce age restrictions.) Jurisdictions typically offer multiple options when self-excluders choose the duration of their ban; some exclusion agreements are in effect for as little as 6 months, while others go to five years and beyond.
A self-exclusion program allows gamblers to opt out, while offering more commitment to that choice than comes from most declarations of abstinence. (Individuals might be able to sign private commitment contracts that also raise the stakes of breaching a no-gambling pledge, and hence potentially provide more motivation to abstain, too; see stickk.com.) Further, the self-exclusion system operates in a fashion that is all but invisible to those satisfied gamblers who choose not to opt out. (A common shortcoming of self-exclusion programs is that they are invisible to problem gamblers, too, in the sense that many regular casino patrons do not know about the existence of self-exclusion schemes.) A more forceful version of an exclusion regime is to alter the default setting so that exclusion is the starting point: adults who want to gamble must opt-in, must take some positive steps to acquire a “license” to gamble. Those positive steps might be quite minor, such as a few days delay between the moment that a license (or “membership” in a casino, perhaps) is applied for and when the license is granted – this was a longtime British casino regulation – or something more involved, including passing an exam indicating that the applicant possesses a basic understanding of probabilities and the likelihood of monetary loss from casino gambling. People who choose not to take the requisite positive steps, then, are thereby self-excluded.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)