Dead by debit.
Earlier remarks have shown that Heidegger does not do much, if any, phenomenology, in the sense of offering descriptions of something for its subsequent analysis. So he has no phenomenology of what it is for something to be missing.
But he has an ontological account of being missing in the sense of “being still outstanding.” “The remainder yet to be received when a debt is to be balanced off, is still outstanding” When the remainder comes successively along, the money comes in to liquidate the debt.(B&T, H 242).
Let me think of this in a small business. If I have $10,000 of a $40,000 debt, $30,000 is still outstanding. That is the sense in which the $30,000 is missing. It is an outstanding part of a totality, i.e., the original $40,000 debt. So my not having the $30,000, is still having it as part of the $40,000 totality.
However, a problem arises when the debtor fails to pay the debt. Suppose he writes it off in bankruptcy. Do we now have a new totality of $10,000 only, the difference between the old totality and the new totality being $30,000?
In accounting, I have to write the debt off. I have to say the money is gone. I have to take a loss. Are we going to subsume the write off, the being gone of the money, the loss, etc., to the difference of the new totality versus the old one?
How do I distinguish the case above from the one in which the $30,000 was never there to pay me back? That would occur in the case where the borrower had no intent to repay the balance. That he intended to pay the $10,000 back as a show of good faith and then leave town. Here my $30,000 is stolen with a false promise.
In the one case, I have a loss to a debtor who just cannot pay, in the other to a crook, who will not pay and told me things that were not true to get my money. Am I indifferent to his lies when I book the loss? One case is in bankruptcy court; the other I might refer to the District Attorney. If I have a board of directors, there might be some furious questions about the latter case, because I, as officer of the company, was taken. There are internal control problems to consider such as how did this man get sold the goods on credit in the first place?
The totality of 'being-still-outstanding' does not account for the difference in the two transactions. In each case, there is a different negative to explain them. In the first case, a business has gone bankrupt and cannot pay me. In the second case, the debtor never meant to pay me. There are two more negatives that need to be turned into positives just to get these cases straight.
In either case, I have to put the loss somewhere. It is a loss, in which my assets are reduced by $30,000 and my equity in my business is reduced by $30,000.
If I do enough of these bad loans, my business is not a going concern. When it is not a going concern is it still a totality? Just a totality of zero? What about the dead phones and my customers who are calling me, missing me as Sartre is missing Pierre? Are the goods that I owe them “still outstanding” for them?
There is a problem for Heidegger in that ‘being still outstanding’ cannot gloss over the negative. A ‘minus’ sign between totalities and the resulting difference does not at all get the drift of what happened.
Nor does it get the drift if I lose $30 outright in a card game. Or if my pocket gets picked. Here again there is no totality at all, and there is no being still outstanding. You have to redefine nothing( i.e., zero, zip, nada) as something, by calling it a totality of nothing, in order to avoid refutation by a simple description of losses.
Philosophy is not won with redefinition. Debates may be; you can sometimes persuade debate judges(even the body politic) with that device. But you cannot do philosophy with it. Once again Heidegger’s position is shown either to be false or tautological(true by definition only).
Sartre makes a similar move with regard to his wallet in which he expects to find 1500 francs and there are only 1300. He bases his argument on a phenomenology of perception and not simple accounting, as in the analysis above. But he has the point, nonetheless. (B&N, 13)
He did not get it from me; I from him.