Human law is a blunt instrument. We often replace the thing that we
actually care about by a proxy for it, because it makes the law easier
to formulate, follow and/or enforce. Thus, to get a driver’s license,
you need to pass a multiple choice test about the rules of the road.
Nobody actually cares whether you can pass the test: what we care about
is whether you know the rules of the road. But the law requires passing
a test, not knowledge.
When a thing is replaced by (sometimes we say “operationalized by”) a
proxy in law, sometimes the law can be practically “exploited”, i.e., it
is possible to literally follow the law while defeating its purpose.
Someone with good test-taking skills might be able to pass a driving
rules test with minimal knowledge (I definitely had a feeling like that
in regard to the test I took).
A multiple-choice test is not a terrible proxy for knowledge, but not
great. Night is a very good proxy for times of significant natural
darkness, but eclipses show it’s not a perfect proxy. In both cases, a
law based on the proxy can be exploited and will in more or less rare
cases have unfortunate consequences.
But whether a law can be practically exploited or not,
pretty much any law involving a proxy will have unfortunate or even
ridiculous consequences in far-out scenarios. For instance, suppose some
jurisdiction defines chronological age as the difference in years
between today’s date and the date of birth, and then has some legal
right that kicks in at age 18. Then if a six-month-old travels to
another stellar system at close to the speed of light, and returns as a
toddler, but 18 years have elapsed on earth, they will have that the
legal rights accruing to an 18-year-old. The difference in years between
today’s date and the date of birth is only a proxy for the chronological
age, but it is a practically nearly perfect proxy—as long as we don’t
have near-light-speed travel.
If a law involves a proxy that does not match the reality we care
about in too common or too easy to engineer
circumstances, then that’s a problem. On the other hand, if the mismatch
happens only in circumstances that the lawmaker knows for sure won’t
actually happen, that’s not an imperfection in the law.
Now suppose that God is the lawmaker. By the above observations, it
does not reflect badly on a lawmaker if a law involves a proxy that
fails only in circumstances that the lawmaker knows for sure won’t
happen. More generally, it does not reflect badly on a lawmaker if a law
has unfortunate or ridiculous consequences in cases that the lawmaker
knows for sure won’t happen. Our experience with human law suggests that
such cases are difficult to avoid without making the law unwieldy. And
while there is no great difficulty for God in making an
unwieldy law, such a law would be hard for us to follow.
In a context where a law is instituted by God (whether by command, or
by desire, or by the choice of a nature for a created person), we thus
should not be surprised if the law “glitches” out in far-out scenarios.
Such “glitches” are no more an imperfection than it is an imperfection
of a helicopter that it can’t fly on the moon. This should put a
significant limitation on the use of counterexamples in ethics (and
likely epistemology) in contexts where we are allowing for the
possibility of a divine institution normativity (say, divine command or
theistic natural law).
One way that this “glitching” can be manifested is this. The moral
law does not present itself to us as just as a random sequence of rules.
Rather, it is an organized body, with more or less vague reasons for the
rules. For instance “Do not murder” and “Do not torture” may come under
a head of “Human life is sacred.” (Compare how US federal law has
“titles” like “Title 17: Copyright” and “Title 52: Voting and
Elections”, and presumably there are vague value-laden principles that
go with the title, such as promoting progress with copyright and giving
voice to people with voting.) In far-out scenarios, the rules may end up
conflicting with their reasons. Thus, to many people “Do not murder”
would not seem a good way to respect to respect the sacredness of human
life in far-out cases where murdering an innocent person is the only way
to save the human race from extinction. But suppose that God in
instituting the law on murder knew for sure that there would never occur
a situation where the only way to save the human race from extinction is
murder. Then there would be no imperfection in making the moral law be
“Do not murder.” Indeed, this would be arguably a better law than “Do
not murder unless the extinction of humanity is at stake”, because the
latter law is needlessly complex if the extinction of humanity
will never be at stake in a potential murder.
Thus the theistic deontologist faced with the question of whether it
would be right to murder if that were the only way to save the human
race can say this: The law prohibits murder even in this case. But if
this case was going to have a chance of happening, then God would likely
have made a different law. Thus, there are two ways of interpreting the
counterfactual question of what would happen if we were in this far-out
situation. We can either keep fixed the moral law, and say that the
murder would be wrong, or we can keep fixed God’s love of human life,
and say that in that case God would likely have made a different law and
so it wouldn’t be wrong.
We should, thus, avoid counterexamples in ethics that involve
situations that we don’t expect to happen, unless our target is an
ethical theory (Kantianism?) that can’t make the above move.
But what about counterexamples in ethics that involve rare
situations that do not make a big overall difference (unlike the case of
the extinction of the human race)? We might think that for the sake of
making the moral law more usable by the limited beings governed by it,
God could have good reason for making laws that in some situations
conflict with the reasons for the laws, as long as these situations are
not of great importance to the human species. (The case of murdering to
prevent the extinction of the human race would be of great importance
even if it were extremely rare!)
If this is right—and I rather wish it isn’t—then the method of
counterexamples is even more limited.