Showing posts with label copyright. Show all posts
Showing posts with label copyright. Show all posts

Monday, December 9, 2024

Hachette v. Internet Archive

I am not a lawyer, but I love constructing counterexamples. I’ve been thinking about the Hachette v. Internet Archive. The Archive scanned a bunch of books they owned, and then lent the scans to users on the Internet, making sure that for each physical book, only one scan was lent at a time. The courts ruled that this was copyright infringement.

I imagine a sequence of cases for a library (the Internet Archive is officially a library in California):

  1. A user comes to the library and reads a book in the ordinary way.

  2. The book is delicate and valuable, so the library puts the book in a metal box with a window, with delicate robotically controlled page flippers controlled by buttons outside the box. The user reads the book through the window while flipping pages with the buttons.

  3. Same as 2, but the user wears glasses.

  4. Same as 2, but the user lives across the street from the library, and the librarian has placed the box in the library window so pointed that the user, and the user alone, can read the book via an ordinary refracting telescope, with the user having buttons connected to the page flippers via long wires.

  5. Same as 4, but the telescope is digital: it has an optical sensor connected electronically to a screen (basically, a CCTV system).

  6. Same as 5, but the optical sensor is inside the library while the digital telescope’s screen is in the user’s home.

  7. Same as 6, but the user can be arbitrarily far away, because wires are very long.

  8. Same as 7, but instead of custom wiring for the connection between the sensor and the screen and the user’s button’s and the page flippers, a TCP/IP protocol over the Internet is employed.

  9. Same as 8, but to reduce wear and tear on the book, the sensor caches the images, so that if the user chooses to jump to a page that has already been viewed, the flippers do not need to operate. The cache is deleted at the end of the session.

  10. Same as 9, but the cache is not deleted at the end of the session, but is kept for the next session with the same user.

  11. Same as 10, but the cache is kept for the next user. Only one user can access the book at once.

  12. Same as 10, but a full cache is generated for all the pages once and for all users. Only one user can operate the system at once.

  13. Same as 11, but the whole cache is copied to the user’s device and removed once the loan period expires.

Here, 12 is pretty much what the Archive was doing when it was letting users download books for a period, and 11 was what they were doing when it was letting users view the books via a browser.

If 11 and 12 are not allowed, at what point do things become impermissible?

If the worry is about there being copying, then there is already copying at 5: the electrical data from the sensor is copied to the screen. If the user flips through the book, the copying is of the book as a whole, though the copies are constantly deleted. But it seems to me (who am not a lawyer) that we shouldn’t make a significant distinction between a digital and an analogue telescope. Moreover, even viewing by eye involves copying. As soon as a page of a book is exposed to light, a large stream of copies of the data in the book appear in the air as patterns of light. Whether these copies are in the air or in glass (as in the case where glasses or an analogue telescope is used) does not seem significant. Is it significant if the data is in electrons rather than photons, as in 5?

Perhaps the worry is about non-evanescent copies. That sounds reasonable. When a book is exposed to light, the copies that are immediately made are evanescent (though very large in quantity), and likewise if a sensor and a screen arrangement (e.g., CCTV) is used. Thus, 1-8 might be distinguished from 9-12, and maybe the caching introduced at 9 is the problem.

However, the Internet and other electronic devices already have caching built in at various levels, so there is already some “hidden” caching introduced at 9, so the existence of caching doesn’t seem that significant. It seems like caching is just an efficiency improvement that does not significantly affect the normative issues.

Thursday, February 15, 2024

Technology and dignitary harms

In contemporary ethics, paternalism is seen as really bad. On the other hand, in contemporary technology practice, paternalism is extremely widely practiced, especially in the name of security: all sorts of things are made very difficult to unlock, with the main official justification being that if if users unlock the things, they open themselves to malware. As someone who always wants to tweak technology to work better for him, I keep on running up against this: I spend a lot of time fighting against software that wants to protect me from my own stupidity. (The latest was Microsoft’s lockdown on direct access to HID data from mice and keyboards when I wanted to remap how my laptop’s touchpad works. Before this, because Chromecasts do not make root access available, to get my TV’s remote control fully working with my Chromecast, I had to make a hardware dongle sitting between the TV and the Chromecast, instead of simply reading the CEC system device on the Chromecast and injecting appropriate keystrokes.)

One might draw one of two conclusions:

  1. Paternalism is not bad.

  2. Contemporary technology practice is ethically really bad in respect of locking things down.

I think both conclusions would be exaggerated. I suspect the truth is that paternalism is not quite as difficult to justify as contemporary ethics makes it out, and that contemporary technology practice is not really bad, but just a little bad in the respect in question, even if that “a little bad” is very annoying to hacker types like me.

Here is another thought. While the official line on a lot of the locking down of hardware and software is that it is for the good of the user, in the name of security, it is likely that often another reason is that walled gardens are seen as profitable in a variety of ways. We think of a profit motive as crass. But at least it’s not paternalistic. Is crass better than paternalistic? On first, thought, surely not: paternalism seeks the good of the customer, while profit-seeking does not. On second thought, it shows more respect for the customer to have a wall around the garden in order to be able to charge admission rather than in order to control the details of the customer’s aesthetic experience for the customer’s own good (you will have a better experience if you start by these oak trees, so we put the gate there and erect a wall preventing you from starting anywhere else). One does have a right to seek reasonable compensation for one’s labor.

The considerations of the last paragraph suggest that the special harm of paternalistic behavior is a dignitary harm. There is no greater non-dignitary harm to me when I am prevented from rooting my device for paternalistic reasons than when I am prevented from doing so for profit reasons, but the dignitary harm is greater in the paternalistic case.

There is, however, an interesting species of dignitary harm that sometimes occurs in profit-motivated technological lockdowns. Some of these lockdowns are motivated by protecting content-creator profits from user piracy. This, too, is annoying. (For instance, when having trouble with one of our TV’s HDMI ports, I tried to solve the difficulty by using an EDID buffer device, but then I could no longer use our Blu-Ray player with that port because of digital-rights management issues.) And here there is a dignitary harm, too. For while paternalistic lockdowns are based on the presumption that lots of users are stupid, copyright lockdowns are based on the presumption that lots of users are immoral.

Objectively, it is worse to be treated as immoral than as stupid: the objective dignitary harm is greater. (But oddly I tend to find myself more annoyed when I am thought stupid than when I am thought immoral. I suppose that is a vice in me.) This suggests that in terms of difficulty of justification of technological lockdowns with respect to dignitary harms, the ordering of motives would be:

  1. Copyright-protection (hardest to justify, with biggest dignitary harm to the user).

  2. Paternalism (somewhat smaller dignitary harm to the user).

  3. Other profit motives (easiest to justify, with no dignitary harm to the user).